Link: http://opinionator.blogs.nytimes.com/2014/04/19/abandon-nearly-all-hope/?_php=true&_type=blogs&_php=true&_type=blogs&_r=1&
With Easter upon us, powerful narratives of rebirth and resurrection are in the air and on the breeze. However, winter’s stubborn reluctance to leave to make way for the pleasing and hopeful season leads me to think not of cherry blossoms and Easter Bunnies but of Prometheus, Nietzsche, Barack Obama and the very roots of hope. Is hope always such a wonderful thing? Is it not rather a form of moral cowardice that allows us to escape from reality and prolong human suffering?
With Easter upon us, powerful narratives of rebirth and resurrection are in the air and on the breeze. However, winter’s stubborn reluctance to leave to make way for the pleasing and hopeful season leads me to think not of cherry blossoms and Easter Bunnies but of Prometheus, Nietzsche, Barack Obama and the very roots of hope. Is hope always such a wonderful thing? Is it not rather a form of moral cowardice that allows us to escape from reality and prolong human suffering?
Is hope
always such a wonderful thing? Is it not rather a form of moral cowardice that
allows us to escape from reality?
Prometheus the Titan was punished by the Olympian
Zeus by being chained to a rock in the Caucasus, quite possibly not that far
from Crimea. Each day for eternity, an eagle pecked out his liver. Every night,
the liver grew back. An unpleasant situation, I’m sure you would agree. His
transgression was to have given human beings the gift of fire and, with that,
the capacity for craft, technological inventiveness and what we are fond of
calling civilization.
This is well known. Less well known is Prometheus’
second gift. In Aeschylus’ “Prometheus Bound,” the chained Titan is pitilessly
interrogated by the chorus. They ask him whether he gave human beings anything
else. Yes, he says, “I stopped mortals from foreseeing doom.” How did you do
that, they ask? His response is revealing: “I sowed in them blind hopes.”
This is a very Greek thought. It stands resolutely opposed to Christianity, with its trinity of faith, love and hope. For St. Paul — Christianity’s true founder, it must be recalled — hope is both a moral attitude of steadfastness and a hope for what is laid up in heaven for us, namely salvation. This is why faith in the resurrection of Jesus Christ is so absolutely fundamental to Christians. Christ died on the cross, but he was resurrected and lives eternally. Jesus is our hope, as Paul writes in the First Letter to Timothy, namely he is the basis for the faith that we too might live eternally. Heaven, as they say, is real.
Photo
CreditLeif
Parsons
In his Letter to the Romans, Paul inadvertently
confirms Prometheus’ gift of blind hope. He asserts that hope in what is seen
is not hope at all, “For who hopes for what he sees?” On the contrary, we
should “hope for what we do not see” and “wait for it with patience.”
Now, fast forward to us. When Barack Obama
describes how he came to write his keynote speech to the 2004 Democratic
National Convention, the speech that instantly shot him to fame and laid the
basis for his presidential campaign and indeed his presidency, he recalls a
phrase that his pastor, the Rev. Jeremiah A. Wright Jr., used in a sermon: the
audacity of hope. Obama says that this audacity is what “was the best of the
American spirit,” namely “the audacity to believe despite all the evidence to
the contrary.”
It is precisely this kind of hope that I think we
should try to give up. It is not audacious, but mendacious. As the wise
Napoleon said, “a leader is a dealer in hope” who governs by insisting on a
bright outlook despite all evidence to the contrary. But what if we looked at
matters differently? What if we expected more from political life than a
four-yearly trade-in of our moral intelligence to one or other of the various
hope dealers that appear on the political market to sell us some shiny new
vehicle of salvation?
The problem here is with the way in which this
audacious Promethean theological idea of hope has migrated into our national
psyche to such an extent that it blinds us to the reality of the world that we
inhabit and causes a sort of sentimental complacency that actually prevents us
from seeing things aright and protesting against this administration’s moral
and political lapses and those of other administrations.
Against the inflated and finally hypocritical
rhetoric of contemporary politics, I think it is instructive to look at things
from another standpoint, an ancient and very Greek standpoint. Just as our
stories shape us as citizens, their stories shaped them and might shape us too.
So, let me tell you a little story, perhaps the most terrifying from antiquity.
In “The History of the Peloponnesian War,”
Thucydides, the sober and unsentimental historian, describes a dialogue between
the representatives of the island of Melos in the Aegean Sea, which was allied
with Sparta, and some ambassadors from invading Athenian military forces. The
ambassadors present the Melians with a very simple choice: Submit to us or be
destroyed.
Rather than simply submit, the Melians wriggle.
They express hope that the Spartans will come to rescue them. The Athenians
calmly point out that it would be an extremely dangerous mission for the
Spartans to undertake and highly unlikely to happen. Also, they add, rightly,
“We are masters of the sea.” The Spartans had formidable land forces, but were
no match for the Athenian navy.
The Melians plead that if they yield to the
Athenians, then all hope will be lost. If they continue to hold out, then “we
can still hope to stand tall.” The Athenians reply that it is indeed true that
hope is a great comfort, but often a delusive one. They add that the Melians
will learn what hope is when it fails them, “for hope is prodigal by nature.”
What we need
in the face of a hard factuality is not hope, but courage in the face of that
reality.
With consummate clarity and no small cruelty, the
Athenians urge the Melians not to turn to Promethean blind hopes when they are
forced to give up their sensible ones. Reasonable hopes can soon become
unreasonable. “Do not be like ordinary people,” they add, “who could use human
means to save themselves but turn to blind hopes when they are forced to give
up their sensible ones – to divination, oracles and other such things that
destroy men by giving them hope.”
At this point, the Athenians withdraw and leave the
Melians to consider their position. As usually happens in political
negotiations, the Melians decide to stick to exactly the same position that
they had adopted before the debate. They explain that “we will trust in the
fortune of the Gods.” In a final statement, the Athenians conclude that “You
have staked everything on your trust in hope … and you will be ruined in
everything.”
After laying siege to the Melian city and some
military skirmishes back and forth, the Athenians lose patience with the
Melians and Thucydides reports with breathtaking understatement, “They killed
all the men of military age and made slaves of the women and children.”
* * *
Thucydides offers no moral commentary on the Melian
Dialogue. He does not tell us how to react, but instead impartially presents us
with a real situation. The dialogue is an argument from power about the nature
of power. This is why Nietzsche, in his polemics against Christianity and
liberalism, loved Thucydides. This is also why I love Nietzsche. Should one
reproach Thucydides for describing the negotiations between the Athenians and
the Melians without immediately moralizing the story and telling us how we
should think? Not at all, Nietzsche insists. What we witness in the Melian
Dialogue is the true character of Greek realism.
Elected regimes can become authoritarian,
democracies can become corrupted, and invading armies usually behave
abominably. What we need in the face of what Nietzsche calls “a strict, hard
factuality,” is not hope, but “courage in the face of reality.”
For Nietzsche, the alternative to Thucydides is
Plato. With his usual lack of moderation, Nietzsche declares that Platonism is
cowardice in the face of reality because it constructs fictional metaphysical
ideals like justice, virtue and the good. Nietzsche sees Platonism as a flight
from the difficulty of reality into a vapid moralistic idealism. Furthermore,
he adds, we have been stuck with versions of moral idealism ever since Plato,
notably in Christianity, with its hope in salvation, and modern liberalism, with
its trust in God and its insistence on hope’s audacity contrary to all
evidence.
RELATED
Read
previous contributions to this series.
Where does this leave us? Rather than see
Thucydides as an apologist for authoritarianism, I see him as a deep but
disappointed democrat with a cleareyed view of democracy’s limitations,
particularly when Athens voted to engage in misplaced military adventures like
the disastrous expedition to Sicily that led to Sparta’s final victory over
Athens in the Peloponnesian Wars. Thucydides would have doubtless had a similar
view of the United States’s military expeditions to countries like Afghanistan
and Iraq on the basis of metaphysical abstractions like enduring freedom or
infinite justice. But he would have thought it was even worse for democracies
to speak out of both sides of their mouths, offering vigorous verbal support
for invaded or embattled peoples and talking endlessly of freedom and hope
while doing precisely nothing.
When democracy goes astray, as it always will, the
remedy should not be some idealistic belief in hope’s audacity, which ends up
sounding either cynical or dogmatic or both. The remedy, in my view, is a
skeptical realism, deeply informed by history. Such realism has an abiding
commitment to reason and the need for negotiation and persuasion, but also an
acute awareness of reason’s limitations in the face of violence and
belligerence. As Thucydides realized long before the 2004 Democratic National
Convention, it is not difficult to make beautiful speeches in politics, but
they very often do little to change people’s minds and effect palpable
improvement in social arrangements.
Thinking without hope might sound rather bleak, but
it needn’t be so. I see it rather as embracing an affirmative, even cheerful,
realism. Nietzsche admired Epictetus, the former slave turned philosophy
teacher, for living without hope. “Yes,” Nietzsche said, “he can smile.” We
can, too.
You can have all kinds of reasonable hopes, it
seems to me, the kind of modest, pragmatic and indeed deliberately fuzzy
conception of social hope expressed by an anti-Platonist philosopher like
Richard Rorty. But unless those hopes are realistic we will end up in a blindly
hopeful (and therefore hopeless) idealism. Prodigal hope invites despair only
when we see it fail. In giving up the former, we might also avoid the latter.
This is not an easy task, I know. But we should try. Nietzsche writes, “Hope is
the evil of evils because it prolongs man’s torment.” Often, by clinging to
hope, we make the suffering worse.
Simon
Critchley is Hans Jonas professor of philosophy at the New School for Social
Research in New York and the author of several books, including “The Ethics of
Deconstruction,” “Stay, Illusion! The Hamlet Doctrine” (with Jamieson Webster)
and the forthcoming “Bowie.” He is the moderator of this series.
No comments:
Post a Comment
Note: Only a member of this blog may post a comment.