Source: http://opinionator.blogs.nytimes.com/2014/04/19/abandon-nearly-all hope/?_php=true&_type=blogs&_php=true&_type=blogs&_r=2&
Abandon (Nearly) All Hope:
SIMON CRITCHLEY
Simon
Critchley is Hans Jonas professor of philosophy at the New School for Social
Research in New York and the author of several books, including “The Ethics of
Deconstruction,” “Stay, Illusion! The Hamlet Doctrine” (with Jamieson Webster)
and the forthcoming “Bowie.” He is the moderator of this series.
With Easter upon us, powerful
narratives of rebirth and resurrection are in the air and on the breeze.
However, winter’s stubborn reluctance to leave to make way for the pleasing and
hopeful season leads me to think not of cherry blossoms and Easter Bunnies but
of Prometheus, Nietzsche, Barack Obama and the very roots of hope. Is hope
always such a wonderful thing? Is it not rather a form of moral cowardice that
allows us to escape from reality and prolong human suffering?
Is
hope always such a wonderful thing? Is it not rather a form of moral cowardice
that allows us to escape from reality?
Prometheus the Titan was punished by the Olympian Zeus by being chained to a rock in the Caucasus, quite possibly not that far from Crimea. Each day for eternity, an eagle pecked out his liver. Every night, the liver grew back. An unpleasant situation, I’m sure you would agree. His transgression was to have given human beings the gift of fire and, with that, the capacity for craft, technological inventiveness and what we are fond of calling civilization.
This is well known. Less well known
is Prometheus’ second gift. In Aeschylus’ “Prometheus Bound,” the chained Titan
is pitilessly interrogated by the chorus. They ask him whether he gave human
beings anything else. Yes, he says, “I stopped mortals from foreseeing doom.”
How did you do that, they ask? His response is revealing: “I sowed in them
blind hopes.”
This is a very Greek thought. It stands resolutely opposed to Christianity, with its trinity of faith, love and hope. For St. Paul — Christianity’s true founder, it must be recalled — hope is both a moral attitude of steadfastness and a hope for what is laid up in heaven for us, namely salvation. This is why faith in the resurrection of Jesus Christ is so absolutely fundamental to Christians. Christ died on the cross, but he was resurrected and lives eternally. Jesus is our hope, as Paul writes in the First Letter to Timothy, namely he is the basis for the faith that we too might live eternally. Heaven, as they say, is real.
This is a very Greek thought. It stands resolutely opposed to Christianity, with its trinity of faith, love and hope. For St. Paul — Christianity’s true founder, it must be recalled — hope is both a moral attitude of steadfastness and a hope for what is laid up in heaven for us, namely salvation. This is why faith in the resurrection of Jesus Christ is so absolutely fundamental to Christians. Christ died on the cross, but he was resurrected and lives eternally. Jesus is our hope, as Paul writes in the First Letter to Timothy, namely he is the basis for the faith that we too might live eternally. Heaven, as they say, is real.
In his Letter to the Romans, Paul
inadvertently confirms Prometheus’ gift of blind hope. He asserts that hope in
what is seen is not hope at all, “For who hopes for what he sees?” On the
contrary, we should “hope for what we do not see” and “wait for it with
patience.”
Now, fast forward to us. When Barack
Obama describes how he came to write his keynote speech to the 2004 Democratic
National Convention, the speech that instantly shot him to fame and laid the
basis for his presidential campaign and indeed his presidency, he recalls a
phrase that his pastor, the Rev. Jeremiah A. Wright Jr., used in a sermon: the
audacity of hope. Obama says that this audacity is what “was the best of the
American spirit,” namely “the audacity to believe despite all the evidence to
the contrary.”
It is precisely this kind of hope
that I think we should try to give up. It is not audacious, but mendacious. As
the wise Napoleon said, “a leader is a dealer in hope” who governs by insisting
on a bright outlook despite all evidence to the contrary. But what if we looked
at matters differently? What if we expected more from political life than a
four-yearly trade-in of our moral intelligence to one or other of the various
hope dealers that appear on the political market to sell us some shiny new
vehicle of salvation?
The problem here is with the way in
which this audacious Promethean theological idea of hope has migrated into our
national psyche to such an extent that it blinds us to the reality of the world
that we inhabit and causes a sort of sentimental complacency that actually
prevents us from seeing things aright and protesting against this
administration’s moral and political lapses and those of other administrations.
Against the inflated and finally
hypocritical rhetoric of contemporary politics, I think it is instructive to
look at things from another standpoint, an ancient and very Greek standpoint.
Just as our stories shape us as citizens, their stories shaped them and might
shape us too. So, let me tell you a little story, perhaps the most terrifying
from antiquity.
In “The History of the Peloponnesian
War,” Thucydides, the sober and unsentimental historian, describes a dialogue
between the representatives of the island of Melos in the Aegean Sea, which was
allied with Sparta, and some ambassadors from invading Athenian military
forces. The ambassadors present the Melians with a very simple choice: Submit
to us or be destroyed.
Rather than simply submit, the
Melians wriggle. They express hope that the Spartans will come to rescue them.
The Athenians calmly point out that it would be an extremely dangerous mission
for the Spartans to undertake and highly unlikely to happen. Also, they add,
rightly, “We are masters of the sea.” The Spartans had formidable land forces,
but were no match for the Athenian navy.
The Melians plead that if they yield
to the Athenians, then all hope will be lost. If they continue to hold out,
then “we can still hope to stand tall.” The Athenians reply that it is indeed
true that hope is a
great comfort, but often a delusive one. They add that the Melians will learn
what hope is when it fails them, “for hope is prodigal by nature.”
What
we need in the face of a hard factuality is not hope, but courage in the face
of that reality.
With consummate clarity and no small
cruelty, the Athenians urge the Melians not to turn to Promethean blind hopes
when they are forced to give up their sensible ones. Reasonable hopes can soon
become unreasonable. “Do not be like ordinary people,” they add, “who could use
human means to save themselves but turn to blind hopes when they are forced to
give up their sensible ones – to divination, oracles and other such things that
destroy men by giving them hope.”
At this point, the Athenians withdraw
and leave the Melians to consider their position. As usually happens in
political negotiations, the Melians decide to stick to exactly the same
position that they had adopted before the debate. They explain that “we will
trust in the fortune of the Gods.” In a final statement, the Athenians conclude
that “You have staked everything on your trust in hope … and you will be ruined
in everything.”
After laying siege to the Melian city
and some military skirmishes back and forth, the Athenians lose patience with
the Melians and Thucydides reports with breathtaking understatement, “They
killed all the men of military age and made slaves of the women and children.”
* * *
Thucydides offers no moral commentary
on the Melian Dialogue. He does not tell us how to react, but instead
impartially presents us with a real situation. The dialogue is an argument from
power about the nature of power. This is why Nietzsche, in his polemics against
Christianity and liberalism, loved Thucydides. This is also why I love
Nietzsche. Should one reproach Thucydides for describing the negotiations
between the Athenians and the Melians without immediately moralizing the story
and telling us how we should think? Not at all, Nietzsche insists. What we
witness in the Melian Dialogue is the true character of Greek realism.
Elected regimes can become
authoritarian, democracies can become corrupted, and invading armies usually
behave abominably. What we need in the face of what Nietzsche calls “a strict,
hard factuality,” is not hope, but “courage in
the face of reality.”
For Nietzsche, the alternative to
Thucydides is Plato. With his usual lack of moderation, Nietzsche declares that
Platonism is cowardice in the face of reality because it constructs fictional
metaphysical ideals like justice, virtue and the good. Nietzsche sees Platonism
as a flight from the difficulty of reality into a vapid moralistic idealism.
Furthermore, he adds, we have been stuck with versions of moral idealism ever
since Plato, notably in Christianity, with its hope in salvation, and modern
liberalism, with its trust in God and its insistence on hope’s audacity
contrary to all evidence.
RELATED
Read previous contributions to this series.
Where does this leave us? Rather than
see Thucydides as an apologist for authoritarianism, I see him as a deep but
disappointed democrat with a cleareyed view of democracy’s limitations,
particularly when Athens voted to engage in misplaced military adventures like
the disastrous expedition to Sicily that led to Sparta’s final victory over
Athens in the Peloponnesian Wars. Thucydides would have doubtless had a similar
view of the United States’s military expeditions to countries like Afghanistan
and Iraq on the basis of metaphysical abstractions like enduring freedom or
infinite justice. But he would have thought it was even worse for democracies
to speak out of both sides of their mouths, offering vigorous verbal support
for invaded or embattled peoples and talking endlessly of freedom and hope
while doing precisely nothing.
When democracy goes astray, as it
always will, the remedy should not be some idealistic belief in hope’s
audacity, which ends up sounding either cynical or dogmatic or both. The
remedy, in my view, is a skeptical realism, deeply informed by history. Such
realism has an abiding commitment to reason and the need for negotiation and
persuasion, but also an acute awareness of reason’s limitations in the face of
violence and belligerence. As Thucydides realized long before the 2004
Democratic National Convention, it is not difficult to make beautiful speeches
in politics, but they very often do little to change people’s minds and effect
palpable improvement in social arrangements.
Thinking without hope might sound
rather bleak, but it needn’t be so. I see it rather as embracing an
affirmative, even cheerful, realism. Nietzsche admired Epictetus, the former
slave turned philosophy teacher, for living without hope. “Yes,” Nietzsche
said, “he can smile.” We can, too.
You can have all kinds of reasonable
hopes, it seems to me, the kind of modest, pragmatic and indeed deliberately
fuzzy conception of social hope expressed by an anti-Platonist philosopher like
Richard Rorty. But unless those hopes are realistic we will end up in a blindly
hopeful (and therefore hopeless) idealism. Prodigal hope invites despair only
when we see it fail. In giving up the former, we might also avoid the latter.
This is not an easy task, I know. But we should try. Nietzsche writes, “Hope is
the evil of evils because it prolongs man’s torment.” Often, by clinging to
hope, we make the suffering worse.
No comments:
Post a Comment
Note: Only a member of this blog may post a comment.